Hands On

Hands On

Patricia S. Churchland [4.28.21]

During my first neuroanatomy lecture, the patient presented to us was a former dean of the medical school who had suffered a small brainstem stroke. As he started to identify the stroke location, the former dean suddenly began to sob piteously. Deeply concerned, we waited in utter stillness a long minute until, abruptly, his sobbing stopped. Unbothered by the interlude, he calmly went on to explain that the episode was caused by the stroke—damage to a tiny region of the brainstem which released reflexive crying when triggered by high levels of adrenalin. Conscious control was futile. A not uncommon sequel of a brainstem stroke, the condition is known as pseudobulbar affect. Adding to our bewilderment, he commented, almost as an aside, that throughout the crying episode he had felt no sadness whatever, though he did admit to finding pseudobulbar affect a nuisance. This was the first result in my new neurophilosophical world: The disconnect between despondent behavior and despondent emotions was the sort of event that many philosophers, trusting entirely in their own imagination, said was inconceivable and could not happen. But it did happen, right before our wondering eyes. This was the first of a host of “philosophically impossible” revelations from brain-damaged patients.

PATRICIA S. CHURCHLAND is professor emeritus of philosophy at the University of California, San Diego, and adjunct professor at the Salk Institute. Her research has centered on the interface between neuroscience and philosophy, with a current focus on the association of morality and the social brain. She is the author of Conscience: The Origins of Moral IntuitionPatricia S. Churchland's Edge Bio Page


HANDS ON

Throwing my anatomy textbook at the wall, I was forced to admit that my goal was doomed. What goal? To teach myself the organization of the thalamus, a brain structure deep under the cortex. Why the thalamus? Because in mammals, all sensory input (except smells) go through the thalamus and from there to cortex. It is kind of the heart and soul of all mammalian brains. In my textbook, each page showed a slice of the thalamus, advancing from back to front, each two millimeters thick. The trouble was, from one page to the next the thalamus looked completely different. From slice to slice, I could not get any sense of continuity, of what this walnut-sized thing really looked like. Visualizing a 3-D thalamus from 2-D illustrations was a dead end. Maybe going whole-hog on real 3-D is a better way. The University of Manitoba has a medical school, and the medical school has a department of brain anatomy. Surely some neuroanatomist can show me what the thalamus looks like.

Cancelling my office hours with students (okay, my bad), I drove my rusty VW downtown and found the neuroanatomy department. The sign on the door read: John Baskerville Hyde, Head. Warmly welcoming the interruption, Hyde listened to my tale of woe with intense interest and encouragement. “Yes,” he agreed, “philosophers need to know about the brain if they want to understand the mind. Here is what we can do. Can you attend regular neuroscience lectures with the first-year medical students? For the lab component, the students will get a human brain to dissect. I will arrange for you to have your own human brain to dissect. Then you’ll begin to learn brain anatomy.”

Heaven had opened its gates to me. Hyde, as it turned out, had studied some philosophy. It emerged that we shared a deep-seated conviction: so-called Conceptual Analysis (aka haggling about meanings of words) might be the conventional philosophical tool, but it was useless for making progress on the actual nature of learning and memory, consciousness and decision-making. You need brain data.

Just like that, after a mere forty minutes conversation, my intellectual life changed forever.

During my first neuroanatomy lecture, the patient presented to us was a former dean of the medical school who had suffered a small brainstem stroke. As he started to identify the stroke location, the former dean suddenly began to sob piteously. Deeply concerned, we waited in utter stillness a long minute until, abruptly, his sobbing stopped. Unbothered by the interlude, he calmly went on to explain that the episode was caused by the stroke—damage to a tiny region of the brainstem which released reflexive crying when triggered by high levels of adrenalin. Conscious control was futile. A not uncommon sequel of a brainstem stroke, the condition is known as pseudobulbar affect. Adding to our bewilderment, he commented, almost as an aside, that throughout the crying episode he had felt no sadness whatever, though he did admit to finding pseudobulbar affect a nuisance. This was the first result in my new neurophilosophical world: The disconnect between despondent behavior and despondent emotions was the sort of event that many philosophers, trusting entirely in their own imagination, said was inconceivable and could not happen. But it did happen, right before our wondering eyes. This was the first of a host of “philosophically impossible” revelations from brain-damaged patients.

Released from the silo of conventional philosophy, I found the neuroscientists at the medical school to be uniformly hospitable and curious about what I was up to. A human brain was indeed delivered to me in the anatomy lab, and holding it my hands, I felt an almost reverential humility toward this tissue that had embodied someone’s love and knowledge and skills. It looked so small, relative to what a human brain can do.

The world of neuroscience was opening up to me. At the clinicians’ weekly meeting—neurology rounds—a patient with unusual or puzzling symptoms would be presented and later discussed. To my everlasting gratitude, the clinicians invited me to join the rounds. One stroke patient was a dairy farmer who could no longer recognize faces—not those of his wife or children, or even his own face in a mirror. Particularly disappointing to him was his inability to recognize the faces of his beloved cows. Because Manitoba is a huge province, and only Winnipeg had advanced medical facilities, any patient with challenging symptoms eventually came to the medical school hospital. I was fortunate to see cases that many neurologists see only rarely, if ever.

Untenured philosophy professors, as was I, are typically advised to avoid risk and stay well-focused on the job. Providentially, my dean, an historian with a dash of intellectual derring-do, skillfully encouraged my hands-on initiative. In time, papers were published, tenure was granted.

From me, the neurologists wanted to know whether philosophers thought there was a nonphysical soul, and if so, why. They were puzzled by those who seemed to regard the human brain simply as hardware on which to run the software of cognition. According to a popular philosophical assumption, to explain the human mind, only the software needs to be understood. Leave the brain out of it. The neurologists knew better; and in time, undermined by accumulating neurobiological evidence, the misbegotten metaphor was quietly shelved.

Neurophilosophy as a paradigm took hold in me because it became gloriously obvious that progress on various time-hallowed philosophical questions, such as how we decide and see and think, was being made in neuroscience. Although prominent philosophers mostly waved off neurophilosophy as “not real philosophy,” this did not matter much to me. The way forward was unmistakable: just follow the science.